Thursday, November 10, 2016

An open letter to those in my family who supported Trump

The following is a lightly-edited message I sent this morning to some people who share my blood. A sizable chunk of these individuals are highly conservative and voted to help elect Donald J. Trump to the Presidency of the United States.
Dear family and former family, 
The following is addressed principally to those members of the group that supported Trump in the 2016 presidential election. I doubt that even the people on my side of the political aisle will be in support of my statements here. 
A couple of weeks back, I had a conversation with one of my brothers about the then-upcoming election. I posed to him a question: "After this is all over, even if Hillary Clinton wins this thing, how can I possibly forgive my Trump-supporting family members?" His answer mirrored my own. 
You and I have had political disagreements in the past. In 2004, in the first election in which I voted, I thought many of you exercised terribly bad judgment by voting for Bush. It never went beyond that, never got intensely personal, with anyone aside from Lynda. I was utterly dismayed when Bush won, but I still came to Myrtle Beach, drank beer with you, and occasionally had a good-natured argument with you.  I thought you were wrong and you thought I was. A relatively simple political disagreement is nothing special. 
In 2008 and 2012, I was happy to vote for Barack Obama. I thought you exercised poor judgment by supporting McCain and/or Romney, but again, I did not begrudge you your choice. Had Obama lost to either of them, I would have been very upset, but I would have recognized that I live to fight another day, and that you are not my enemy. 
This time it is different. What you have done is monstrous and unforgivable. I will not bother enumerating the myriad reasons why, because they are and have been obvious and clearly do not matter to you. Whether you justify your actions based on some abstract principles of conservatism, or because you could not see a relevant difference between the candidates, or because you have an irrational hatred of the Clintons... none of it matters to me. 
There is no excuse for what has happened. 
I will not speak to you ever again in any capacity. I will not acknowledge your existence. You are dead to me. I understand that this is likely no great loss for you, but it's not meant to be a punishment anyway. I know that in this time in American history it may be ill-advised to burn bridges, but consider them ashes. 
Do not approach me. Do not talk to me. Do not approach or talk to my son. Emilie [my wife] can obviously speak for herself, but I suspect that she'd be a lot happier if you avoided her as well. Do not bother to email me back, as I will not read it, and I will delete the email like I would any other bit of spam. We are done here. 
Everyone and anyone who supported Hillary and opposed Trump in this election: You are welcome to email me and tell me that I should not despair, or that I am an asshole, or that this message is overkill, or that you agree, or whatever. I love you, and I will gladly read and respond to anything you have to say. Good luck out there. You and I will need it.

Tuesday, September 13, 2016

Fred Tuesdays 9.13.2016

A blogger writing about reinforcement schedules and their relation to the world at large occasionally goes for very long periods of time between new posts. There's a joke in there somewhere.

Evidently, I have abandoned the practice of posting new Skinner quotes on Fridays. No matter, I will just post new quotes "whenever I feel like it," whatever that means.

I am currently teaching a freshman seminar on the topics of freedom and determinism. My general thoughts on these matters should be obvious, but I try to maintain something approaching a neutral stance when it comes to working with my students. Something that has come up already this semester is in the notion that something important may be lost when we see the (deterministic) mechanisms by which things we call beautiful are revealed. By this view, peeking behind the curtain reveals the trick behind the magic and ruins the illusion.

Pay no attention to the man behind the curtain... or else lose your autonomy!

This is largely the sort of argument that many proponents of creationism are implicitly making when they deny Darwinian evolution. It's often, though not always, an appeal to a kind of "bugbear" (Dennett, 1984) wherein the truth of an argument takes a backseat to the horror of its being true, and the prescription reveals itself in denial.

I find that the following passage from Beyond Freedom and Dignity rings true.

Nothing is changed because we look at it, talk about it, or analyze it in a new way. Keats drank confusion to Newton for analyzing the rainbow, but the rainbow remained as beautiful as ever and became for many even more beautiful. Man has not changed because we look at him, talk about him, and analyze him scientifically. His achievements in science, government, religion, art, and literature remain as they have always been, to be admired as one admires a storm at sea or autumn foliage or a mountain peak...

Friday, June 17, 2016

Fred Fridays 6.17.2016

We are all controlled by the world in which we live, and part of that world has been and will be constructed by men. The question is this: Are we to be controlled by accident, by tyrants, or by ourselves in effective cultural design?

The danger or the misuse of power is possibly greater than ever. It is not allayed by disguising the facts. We cannot make wise decisions if we continue to pretend that human behavior is not controlled, or if we refuse to engage in control when valuable results might be forthcoming. Such measures weaken only ourselves, leaving the strength of science to others. The first step in a defense against tyranny is the fullest possible exposure of controlling techniques. A second step has already been taken successfully in restricting the use of physical force. Slowly, and as yet imperfectly, we have worked out an ethical and governmental design in which the strong man is not allowed to use the power deriving from his strength to control his fellow men. He is restrained by a superior force created for that purpose - the ethical pressure of the group, or more explicit religious and governmental measures. We tend to distrust superior forces, as we currently hesitate to relinquish sovereignty in order to set up an international police force. But it is only through such counter-control that we have achieved what we call peace - a condition in which men are not permitted to control each other through force. In other words, control itself must be controlled.

From "Freedom and the Control of Men,"(1955)

Friday, June 10, 2016

Charlie Fridays 6.10.2016

I was reading an article written by A.C. Catania (1992), noteworthy behaviorist and a colleague of Skinner's for many years, and came across a passage that I absolutely love. I have had many arguments with those that declare that cognitive processes are independent of behavior, that suggest that whatever one is doing when they are thinking is different than what they do when they are acting. I have tried, with varying success, to dissuade them of this position. This passage puts it better than I ever have.
Most processes called 'cognitive' (e.g., imagining or visualizing) are private events. We cannot see what someone else is imagining, but imagining, like walking or talking, is something we do. Some might argue that these private events should not be called behavior. Yet behavior is not limited to movements. It is plausible to assume that imagining shares something with the behavior of looking at things (we can discriminate our imagining from our seeing; when we fail to do so, we are said to have hallucinations; cf. Skinner, 1953).

Friday, June 3, 2016

On representations, storage, and metaphor

Last month, former Skinner graduate student and radical behaviorist Robert Epstein published an article on Aeon that served as an attack on the Information Processing (IP) metaphor that is ubiquitous in cognitive science. The basic idea behind the IP metaphor is that the brain functions in ways appreciably similar to computers – there is input to the system, and there is output from the system, and in between there is varying number of intermediate, internal steps wherein the data is “processed,” whatever that means. Portions of these internal steps are necessarily related to the concepts of intervening variables, expectations, memory, and mental representations.

A modern variant of the old telephone switchboard metaphor and just as accurate.
Epstein, like Skinner before him, challenged the validity and the usefulness of the metaphor. He attacked it from a few angles. I think some of his punches were ill-advised, because they allowed critics (of which there have been many) to focus on issues that are ultimately unimportant for understanding the behaviorist’s perspective on human action, memory, and the like. For example, Epstein shows a lack of expertise in defining the operations of computers. This was a misstep, but frankly it is one that matters very little. Here, I will address what I consider to be the core issue at hand. It is not whether brains are computers. The core issue is one of representation and storage. Does the organism store memories in the forms of representations, and if so, how does this factor into the animal’s behavior?

Let’s look to a simple example. A hungry rat is released into a maze. It has never been in this maze before, but it is a typical rat and soon begins to “explore” the environment. Eventually, it comes across the end of the maze, where there is a small box with sugar pellets inside. The rat eats, and the researcher removes it from the maze. Later, the still-hungry rat is released again into the same maze. As before, it traverses the maze (more quickly this time), gets to the sugar, eats, and is removed once again. And so on, and so forth, over repeated trials spread across days. You will be unsurprised to learn that the rat becomes faster in this task across trials. In my experience with rudimentary mazes, the rat may require several minutes before reaching the goal box on early trials, but may require only mere seconds following the appropriate training regimen.

What do many cognitive scientists want to say about this? It is not simply that the animal’s behavior of “reaching the goal box” has been reinforced (and wrong turns punished), and therefore the behavior becomes more likely and quicker. Instead, the cognitivist may suggest that the well-trained rat has acquired representations both of the maze and of the sugar, and upon being released into the maze, has these representations activated. The animal “remembers” that sugar is available. The animal “expects” to find sugar at the end of the maze. The animal “knows” the layout of the maze, or has “acquired a cognitive map” of the environment. That the animal becomes more proficient on the task is only incidentally related to its training regimen, as the behavior on any given trial is a product of these mental constructs (of representation, of memory, of expectation).

And this seems at first glance to be entirely reasonable, does it not? After all, each of us knows what it means to have a memory, to work towards goals, to know what an environment looks like. It is not so difficult to imagine that such things could exist in some form for rats as well as we humans. This, of course, requires that our intuitions regarding our own mental lives and their role in our behavior are accurate. Suffice it to say that there is good reason to think such introspective “knowledge” is fundamentally mistaken.

To simply illustrate this point, let us consider another simple experiment. An experimenter affixes a small tube adjacent to a rabbit’s eye through which air may be passed. A pulse of air to the eye is an irritant, and causes the rabbit to blink. This is a simple reflex. The experimenter then presents a series of trials wherein a brief auditory stimulus immediately precedes the delivery of a pulse of air (e.g., ClickàPulse trials). Initially, the animal will only blink when the jet of air is applied, but after a number of trials will begin to blink when the click occurs. The blink response to the click is learned. A novel and dissimilar stimulus (e.g., a tone or a flashing light) will not produce this blinking response. Students of learning recognize this to be a very common form of Pavlovian conditioning, and it works equally well in human beings. Conditioning someone to blink to an auditory stimulus is a common exercise in Introductory Psychology classes. Importantly, that one blinks to the click is irrespective of their “volition.” The response is what some term involuntary. Even if one actively tries to not blink, they will typically fail.

I wonder if the rat is acquiring a representation of my elbow here.
How to explain this phenomenon? We could suggest, as with the maze running example above, that the animal has acquired representations of the air pulse and of the click. The click stimulus activates a representation of the air pulse (which must be stored within the reflex pathway), and it is this representation that somehow causes the animal to blink. Importantly, the click must be “known” by the organism as well, so a representation of the click must be stored somewhere too – if it was not, then the click could not possibly selectively activate the representation of the air pulse.

The problems, as I see them, are that appealing to representational structures accomplishes nothing more than does appealing to the observed interactions between the organism and the environment, is far more opaque to scientific inquiry, and when taken to its logical conclusion is absurd. For example…

What about innate reflexes? Do we need to posit that a person has within himself a representation of a patellar tap to account for the fact that his leg involuntarily kicks when a doctor raps the knee? If not, then why is it necessary for any other kind of behavior? What are the pertinent differences that make the invocation of representations appropriate in one domain of behavior, but not another?

Where is the representation of the knee-tap stored?
Note that I am not arguing that there are no differences between a reflexive leg-kick and the behavior of traversing a maze. There are differences, but they are not obviously relevant to a conversation about representational structures. Precisely why these actions are different cannot be explained by appeal to such structures, but can only be explained by the analysis of the contingencies that produce each of them. The former is a product of ancestral contingencies, while the latter is a product of personal reinforcement contingencies - both these causes are environmental, but the exact environment that has control is different.

Organisms are changed by virtue of their contact with an environment. An experience today may have measurable effects on behavior tomorrow, but that does not mean that the experience was somehow stored within the organism. The experience, rather, changes the organism such that they are more likely to respond in a particular way at a later time. Appealing to internal representations gets us no closer to understanding this phenomenon. Referring to the relevant phenomena with the use of the storage and IP metaphors obscures what actually takes place when an organism behaves. These practices appear to serve both as an inaccurate proxy for actual knowledge and to preserve the organism’s privileged status as the originator of its behavior. If a natural account of human behavior is to be attained, we must jettison both mental constructs and metaphor.

Fred Fridays 6.3.2016

From his Notebooks (1980, p. 360):

"I used to represent the behaviorist's attitude toward himself by describing a lecturer who explains human behavior, including the behavior of other lecturers, and leaves the stage. Then he sticks his head out from the wings and says, 'And I'm like that too!'"


Friday, March 11, 2016

Fred Fridays

At bottom, the following represents a main implication of radical behaviorism. Skinner once remarked that the argument he put forth in Beyond Freedom and Dignity was so convincing that he no longer felt any measure of responsibility, of ownership, of the work. Adoption of the position requires that one cedes pride in their work, as whatever one does is necessarily a product of an individual's personal and ancestral environmental histories, neither of which is under the control of the individual in question.

"I did not direct my life. I didn't design it. I never made decisions. Things always came up and made them for me. That's what life is."

Stop saying that "X" changes the brain

If you pay any attention to media coverage of novel medical and neuropsychological research, you will come into frequent contact with a particular sort of claim. Namely, that something changes the brain. That something could be any number of different things, depending on the news of the day and the predilections of the source.

Want evidence? OK.

How does reading pop-science articles on the changing brain change the brain?
That took all of two seconds. You can get more specific with your history, too, if you want to have some fun with that. Does eating ice cream change the brain? Does breathing pure oxygen change the brain? Do battles with irritable bowel syndrome change the brain?

Here's the thing, everyone - everything changes the brain. I had a latte and an empanada earlier today, and I can tell you with absolute certainty that doing so changed my brain. How can I be so certain? Because I am able to relay to you the fact that I did it. I have been changed in a manner that results in my ability to describe the experience, what most would call "memory." To say that any given experience "X" changes the brain is to say nothing of importance. You'd be harder-pressed to find an experience that doesn't result in the brain changing. 

Is it worthwhile to know how the brain changes as a result of experience? In other words, should we study which regions may be more affected by particular sorts of experience, or how neurotransmitter release differs by exogenous factors, and the like? Sure. This kind of information has its uses. But the general statement about any particular event changing the brain is absolutely pointless and you would be better served saving your breath.

Monday, February 29, 2016

Donald Trump and his supporters

In the throes of the Presidential primary races, there is a great deal to discuss with respect to Donald Trump's behavior and that of his followers. Needless to say, there is much by which to be disturbed. Many others have noted the relevant issues that thoughtful individuals ought to have regarding Trump, his popularity, and what the whole circus means for the country, and so I do not have to really get into it here.

However, I was reading Contingencies of Reinforcement: A Theoretical Analysis (1969) early this morning and came across a wonderful passage that strikes me as relevant. In Chapter 2, "Utopia as an experimental culture," Skinner writes:
The man who insists upon judging a culture in terms of whether or not he likes it is the true immoralist. Just as he refuses to follow rules designed to maximize his own net gain because they conflict with immediate gratification, so he rejects contingencies designed to strengthen the group because they conflict with his "rights as an individual." He sets himself up as a standard of human nature, implying or insisting that the culture which produced him is the only good or natural culture. He wants the world he wants and is unwilling to ask why he wants it. He is so completely the product of his own culture that he fears the influence of any other. He is like the child who said: "I'm glad I don't like broccoli because if I liked it, I'd eat a lot of it, and I hate it."
The connections to many current political hot-button topics are clear. Those that currently stand in the way of social and political progress are as petulant and myopic as the child described above.

Friday, February 19, 2016

Fred Fridays

Beginning today, I will be posting interesting quotations from B.F. Skinner (casually known as Fred) once a week on Fridays. Sometimes these quotes will just be quirky passages from a man who is not recognized for being as funny as he really was. Most of the time, though, I will strive to post poignant, prescient quotes that reflect on our current problems in either psychological science or in society as a whole.

The latest news from NASA indicates that we have yet again broken a global temperature record (January 2016 being the hottest first month of the year in recorded history). The indication continues to be that we humans will do almost nothing about it. This is, of course, related to the explicit denial of any such problem by a huge swath of the population and the politicians it supports. This portion of the population identifies overwhelmingly as politically conservative, a group that often proudly elevates the so-called rights of the individual as being paramount, perhaps even near-sacred. Such a focus may prove disastrous for the globe, as the Anthropocene geological era continues apace.

To wit: Skinner (1979) writes in "The Steep and Thorny Way to a Science of Behavior,"
In the long run, the aggrandizement of the individual jeopardizes the future of the species and the culture. In effect, it infringes the so-called rights of billions of people still to be born, in whose interests only the weakest of sanctions are now maintained. We are beginning to realize the magnitude of the problem of bringing human behavior under the control of a projected future, and we are already suffering from the fact that we have come very late to recognize that mankind will have a future only if it designs a viable way of life.