Friday, June 17, 2016

Fred Fridays 6.17.2016

We are all controlled by the world in which we live, and part of that world has been and will be constructed by men. The question is this: Are we to be controlled by accident, by tyrants, or by ourselves in effective cultural design?

The danger or the misuse of power is possibly greater than ever. It is not allayed by disguising the facts. We cannot make wise decisions if we continue to pretend that human behavior is not controlled, or if we refuse to engage in control when valuable results might be forthcoming. Such measures weaken only ourselves, leaving the strength of science to others. The first step in a defense against tyranny is the fullest possible exposure of controlling techniques. A second step has already been taken successfully in restricting the use of physical force. Slowly, and as yet imperfectly, we have worked out an ethical and governmental design in which the strong man is not allowed to use the power deriving from his strength to control his fellow men. He is restrained by a superior force created for that purpose - the ethical pressure of the group, or more explicit religious and governmental measures. We tend to distrust superior forces, as we currently hesitate to relinquish sovereignty in order to set up an international police force. But it is only through such counter-control that we have achieved what we call peace - a condition in which men are not permitted to control each other through force. In other words, control itself must be controlled.

From "Freedom and the Control of Men,"(1955)

Friday, June 10, 2016

Charlie Fridays 6.10.2016

I was reading an article written by A.C. Catania (1992), noteworthy behaviorist and a colleague of Skinner's for many years, and came across a passage that I absolutely love. I have had many arguments with those that declare that cognitive processes are independent of behavior, that suggest that whatever one is doing when they are thinking is different than what they do when they are acting. I have tried, with varying success, to dissuade them of this position. This passage puts it better than I ever have.
Most processes called 'cognitive' (e.g., imagining or visualizing) are private events. We cannot see what someone else is imagining, but imagining, like walking or talking, is something we do. Some might argue that these private events should not be called behavior. Yet behavior is not limited to movements. It is plausible to assume that imagining shares something with the behavior of looking at things (we can discriminate our imagining from our seeing; when we fail to do so, we are said to have hallucinations; cf. Skinner, 1953).

Friday, June 3, 2016

On representations, storage, and metaphor

Last month, former Skinner graduate student and radical behaviorist Robert Epstein published an article on Aeon that served as an attack on the Information Processing (IP) metaphor that is ubiquitous in cognitive science. The basic idea behind the IP metaphor is that the brain functions in ways appreciably similar to computers – there is input to the system, and there is output from the system, and in between there is varying number of intermediate, internal steps wherein the data is “processed,” whatever that means. Portions of these internal steps are necessarily related to the concepts of intervening variables, expectations, memory, and mental representations.

A modern variant of the old telephone switchboard metaphor and just as accurate.
Epstein, like Skinner before him, challenged the validity and the usefulness of the metaphor. He attacked it from a few angles. I think some of his punches were ill-advised, because they allowed critics (of which there have been many) to focus on issues that are ultimately unimportant for understanding the behaviorist’s perspective on human action, memory, and the like. For example, Epstein shows a lack of expertise in defining the operations of computers. This was a misstep, but frankly it is one that matters very little. Here, I will address what I consider to be the core issue at hand. It is not whether brains are computers. The core issue is one of representation and storage. Does the organism store memories in the forms of representations, and if so, how does this factor into the animal’s behavior?

Let’s look to a simple example. A hungry rat is released into a maze. It has never been in this maze before, but it is a typical rat and soon begins to “explore” the environment. Eventually, it comes across the end of the maze, where there is a small box with sugar pellets inside. The rat eats, and the researcher removes it from the maze. Later, the still-hungry rat is released again into the same maze. As before, it traverses the maze (more quickly this time), gets to the sugar, eats, and is removed once again. And so on, and so forth, over repeated trials spread across days. You will be unsurprised to learn that the rat becomes faster in this task across trials. In my experience with rudimentary mazes, the rat may require several minutes before reaching the goal box on early trials, but may require only mere seconds following the appropriate training regimen.

What do many cognitive scientists want to say about this? It is not simply that the animal’s behavior of “reaching the goal box” has been reinforced (and wrong turns punished), and therefore the behavior becomes more likely and quicker. Instead, the cognitivist may suggest that the well-trained rat has acquired representations both of the maze and of the sugar, and upon being released into the maze, has these representations activated. The animal “remembers” that sugar is available. The animal “expects” to find sugar at the end of the maze. The animal “knows” the layout of the maze, or has “acquired a cognitive map” of the environment. That the animal becomes more proficient on the task is only incidentally related to its training regimen, as the behavior on any given trial is a product of these mental constructs (of representation, of memory, of expectation).

And this seems at first glance to be entirely reasonable, does it not? After all, each of us knows what it means to have a memory, to work towards goals, to know what an environment looks like. It is not so difficult to imagine that such things could exist in some form for rats as well as we humans. This, of course, requires that our intuitions regarding our own mental lives and their role in our behavior are accurate. Suffice it to say that there is good reason to think such introspective “knowledge” is fundamentally mistaken.

To simply illustrate this point, let us consider another simple experiment. An experimenter affixes a small tube adjacent to a rabbit’s eye through which air may be passed. A pulse of air to the eye is an irritant, and causes the rabbit to blink. This is a simple reflex. The experimenter then presents a series of trials wherein a brief auditory stimulus immediately precedes the delivery of a pulse of air (e.g., ClickàPulse trials). Initially, the animal will only blink when the jet of air is applied, but after a number of trials will begin to blink when the click occurs. The blink response to the click is learned. A novel and dissimilar stimulus (e.g., a tone or a flashing light) will not produce this blinking response. Students of learning recognize this to be a very common form of Pavlovian conditioning, and it works equally well in human beings. Conditioning someone to blink to an auditory stimulus is a common exercise in Introductory Psychology classes. Importantly, that one blinks to the click is irrespective of their “volition.” The response is what some term involuntary. Even if one actively tries to not blink, they will typically fail.

I wonder if the rat is acquiring a representation of my elbow here.
How to explain this phenomenon? We could suggest, as with the maze running example above, that the animal has acquired representations of the air pulse and of the click. The click stimulus activates a representation of the air pulse (which must be stored within the reflex pathway), and it is this representation that somehow causes the animal to blink. Importantly, the click must be “known” by the organism as well, so a representation of the click must be stored somewhere too – if it was not, then the click could not possibly selectively activate the representation of the air pulse.

The problems, as I see them, are that appealing to representational structures accomplishes nothing more than does appealing to the observed interactions between the organism and the environment, is far more opaque to scientific inquiry, and when taken to its logical conclusion is absurd. For example…

What about innate reflexes? Do we need to posit that a person has within himself a representation of a patellar tap to account for the fact that his leg involuntarily kicks when a doctor raps the knee? If not, then why is it necessary for any other kind of behavior? What are the pertinent differences that make the invocation of representations appropriate in one domain of behavior, but not another?

Where is the representation of the knee-tap stored?
Note that I am not arguing that there are no differences between a reflexive leg-kick and the behavior of traversing a maze. There are differences, but they are not obviously relevant to a conversation about representational structures. Precisely why these actions are different cannot be explained by appeal to such structures, but can only be explained by the analysis of the contingencies that produce each of them. The former is a product of ancestral contingencies, while the latter is a product of personal reinforcement contingencies - both these causes are environmental, but the exact environment that has control is different.

Organisms are changed by virtue of their contact with an environment. An experience today may have measurable effects on behavior tomorrow, but that does not mean that the experience was somehow stored within the organism. The experience, rather, changes the organism such that they are more likely to respond in a particular way at a later time. Appealing to internal representations gets us no closer to understanding this phenomenon. Referring to the relevant phenomena with the use of the storage and IP metaphors obscures what actually takes place when an organism behaves. These practices appear to serve both as an inaccurate proxy for actual knowledge and to preserve the organism’s privileged status as the originator of its behavior. If a natural account of human behavior is to be attained, we must jettison both mental constructs and metaphor.

Fred Fridays 6.3.2016

From his Notebooks (1980, p. 360):

"I used to represent the behaviorist's attitude toward himself by describing a lecturer who explains human behavior, including the behavior of other lecturers, and leaves the stage. Then he sticks his head out from the wings and says, 'And I'm like that too!'"